A paper I wrote for my
philosophy of classical physics course at
University of Kentucky (fall 2000). I wrote it in about four of five hours, so it's not that great. But anyway...
Introduction
Because it requires so little
conceptual baggage, because it is so
easy to understand, and because it so deeply touches upon our desire
to know what it is to be
human, the question of
free will is one of
the oldest of
philosophy. From the beginning of human
civilisation,
people have wondered about
fate,
destiny, and the role these play in
their lives. Around the
sixteenth century, Western culture began to
develop sophisticated systems of
physics which hoped to some day
explain everything. The
data and
knowledge all seemed to point to a
single result---that the universe behaves in a very
mechanistic manner.
However, if that is truly the case, where does free will fit in? Is
the human
soul somehow able to
influence the
world in a
nondeterministic way? Is our free will merely
illusory?
Philosophers have tried, and are still trying, to answer important
questions such as these.
For the purposes of our discussion, we must define some important
terms. Physics is the system we use for describing and prediction the
behaviour of matter and energy. The appellation ``classical physics''
is given to physics predating quantum mechanics. Quantum mechanics
and related physics fall under the designation of ``modern physics''.
Determinism is the belief that all physical events are precisely
determined by external forces before they occur (The Ism
Book). Free will is the ability of an object---usually a
mind---to determine its own course of action. Alternately, it is the
belief that such ability exists, and can be attributed to the human
mind. Finally, compatibilism is the claim that free will and
determinism are not, in fact, mutually exclusive. This view is also
known as ``reconciliationism'' (Dennett).
Views on classical physics
Some of the earliest philosophical
theories of free will in
our
intellectual tradition were those of the
Epicureans and the
Stoics. The Epicurean
atomists, who were in general surprisingly
in agreement with today's
science, generally claimed that the
atoms of which the
universe was constructed
behaved
mechanistically. However, they claimed that these atoms could
occasionally make
random swerves, and that allowed for free will
(Dennett). Stoics were, on the other hand,
fatalistic
and
deterministic, and claimed that our free will resided in our
ability to
adjust our expectations down to meet what was
determined
by fate. That these two
opposite views have not be
reconciled to
this day demonstrates how tricky a
question free will is.
Later, in the seventeenth century, the search for a mechanical
description of the world grew stronger. René Descartes claimed not
only that inanimate objects behaved deterministically, but also that
animals were nothing more than automata. Descartes'
dualism posited the existence of only two substances: matter and
spirit. According to him, the two substances could never
interact---except in the human soul or mind. Spirit could,
through the soul, influence the matter of the brain, and thereby the
nerves, muscles, and finally the world outside the body.
According to Descartes, our vivid sensation of free will is enough
evidence to show that it must be true (Descartes). Since matter behaves
deterministically, and determinism (according to most
philosophers, especially Descartes and his contemporaries and
predecessors) is contradictory with free will, the free will of
the human soul must come from the spirit and not the matter.
Another early rationalist who argued on the question of free will
was Baruch Spinoza. Spinoza went further than Descartes with his
determinism. Unlike the dualists, he did not posit humans (or
animals, or anything) as an exception to physical determinism. In
his Ethics, he proves from some basic axioms that the
universe is deterministic and that free will does not exist. He
derives from his seven axioms Proposition XXVI: ``A thing which has
been determined to any action was necessarily so determined by God,
and that which has not been determined by God cannot determined itself
to action''; this seems to indicate determinism, or at the very
least a lack of free will. He proceeds to make this denial of free
will more explicit with Proposition XXXII, ``The will cannot be
called a free cause, but only necessary''. He, in fact, goes
beyond determinism in the Ethics. He claims, in his
Proposition XXXIII: ``Things could have been produced by God in no
other manner and in no other order than that in which they have
been produced'' (Spinoza). That is, not only can things proceed only in
a certain way in this universe, but they could not proceed differently
in any universe. Thus, this world is the only possible one.
Opposed to both Spinoza and Descartes was Leibniz. According to
this philosopher, though most bodies behave deterministically, there
also exist more concentrated bodies, called minds or souls. These
have at least the appearance of free will: ``There is no creature
. . . who could predict with certainty what another mind would
choose . . . as it can be predicted in another case, at least by an
angel, how some body will act if the course of nature not be
interrupted'' (Leibniz). That is, the free will of human souls
prevents a purely deterministic account of the universe. No created
being could predict the behaviour of a human mind. However, he does
not claim to infringe on God's omniscience: ``This does not,
however, prevent the future actions of the mind . . . from being
fixed by God''. Thus Leibniz may actually believe free will to be
illusory: it is necessarily impossible that we be able to
predict the behaviour of another mind, but the future actions of
that mind are known by God and hence fixed.
Leibniz also believes that there is no causal correlation between
thoughts and physical actions, but rather that God ensures
``harmony'' between mental and physical states
(Wilson). This is in direct opposition to Descartes'
dualism, which states that the mind directly influences the brain.
Thus Leibniz allows free will to coëxist with determinism, though it
is determinism of a most peculiar sort.
Immanuel Kant, in his Prolegomena to Any Future
Metaphysics, presents as one of the classical
antinomies of physics the questions of free will. His
third antinomy consists, in his own words, of the thesis that, on the
one hand, ``There are in the World Causes through Freedom'', and
that, on the other hand, ``There is no Liberty, only Nature''.
According to Kant, ``the opposed assertions . . . may both be true''.
He resolves the contradiction by claiming that it applies concepts
applicable only to facts to perceptions. According to section 53
of his \emph{Prolegomena}, ``If natural necessity is referred merely
to appearances, and freedom merely to things in
themselves, no contradiction arises . . . . Nature therefore and
freedom can without contradiction be attributed to the very same
thing, but in different relations---on one side as phenomenon, on
the other as a thing in itself''.
Modern physics
The beginning of the
twentieth century saw the development of a new
system of
physics which flew in the face of
established Western
scientific thought. The theorists of
quantum mechanics (
QM), in
response to questions about
black-body radiation and the
photoelectric effect, began to develop a system of physics in which
energy could be described solely in
integral units. Though at
first
innocuous, quantum mechanics soon posed serious questions about
the
nature of being.
One important result in quantum mechanics is the Heisenberg
uncertainty principle (HUP). According to HUP, there exist pairs of
quantum numbers such that, the more precisely one measures the one,
the less precisely one knows the value of the other. The most common
examples given are position and velocity, though other such
quantum pairs exist (Omnes). This absolute limitation on
our knowledge seems to spell doom for the ability to use physics
to accurately predict the future.
Another important aspect of QM is the role of the observer.
According to some interpretations of QM, the observer plays a
significant role in the behaviour of physical entities. Without
some kind of observer measuring certain quantities, it appears that
those quantities are never in fact precisely determined. This
raises the question of what, precisely, is an ``observer'', and
whether the behaviour---or the very existence---of the universe
depends intrinsically on the human mind. Here is a major blow
against determinism---or at least for compatibilism. If the
events of the universe depend on the actions of minds, it appears we
have a way for free will to influence the universe without
somewhere violating the laws of physics. However, such a result is
rather unsavoury to physicists. Some have claimed that, in this
context, an object may collapse a waveform as an ``observer'' if
the possible results of that collapse are sufficiently distinct
(Penrose). Unfortunately, this question lies outside the
realms of physics, since it is impossible to obtain useful information
from an experiment that we never observe.
Free will and determinism
Though they are generally considered to be
mutually exclusive, it is
possible to provide a
framework in which
determinism and
free
will coëxist. There is, however, a major
paradox that must be
answered first: suppose the universe is
deterministic, and we can
perform some
calculation to
predict any
future state of an
object given the
universe's
current state. Then, if we have
free will, we should be able to
subvert these
predictions---if
physics
predicts I will raise my
right hand at
time T, I may
choose not to, and vice versa. There is no reason why the mere
process of prediction should
restrict my ability to raise or not
raise my hand, so I in fact do not possess free will
with respect to
raising my hand. Since we could perform the same calculations for any
action I might
perform,
I do not possess free will at all.
There are a number of ways of dealing with this problem. The first is
Leibniz's solution: to say that, though it be fixed in God's eyes,
the course of action of a human mind is unpredictable to anything
other than God. This is a rather weak response, though, as it
appears to be an ad hoc attempt to reconcile free will with
divine omnipotence, and does not completely address the topic of
physical determinism. It is a complete solution to the problem
only if we can show that divine omnipotence implies
determinism---which has not been demonstrated sufficiently for our
purposes.
There is another way we can use a similar response. Anything which
would be doing the prediction---be it a human mind, a computer, or
something else---must be able to influence the rest of the world.
After all, if it were not, there would be no paradox: I would not
know of the prediction, so I would not be able to deliberately
choose to violate it. Since the predicting object would be
influencing the world, it must take its own actions into
account---otherwise, it introduces a margin of error which may be
large enough to allow a decision. In order to measure how it
influences the rest of the world, though, the object must somehow
precisely represent itself; then, though, it must precisely
represent the representation, and so on ad infinitum. This,
though, requires the object to be infinitely complex and infinitely
fast (if it is to predict its influence on the world before it
exerts that influence). Thus such an object is logically
impossible, as is predicting the future course of the universe.
There is still a problem with this resolution of the paradox,
though. We have shown that determinism does not, at least in this
method, eliminate the possibility of free will, but we have not
shown how free will might exist in such a universe---how does free
mind influence matter? What in our physics allows this to happen?
We may resort to Lucretius's ``swerves'' or to uncertain quantum
behaviour, but we still cannot find a mechanism that would allow such
influence. Here, one may result to observer-dependence of quantum
events---by observing certain things and not others, we in fact
cause things to happen. Thus we may influence the world in ways
consistent with a mostly deterministic physics.
Conclusion
The
world appears to
behave, on a
large scale, mostly
deterministically. This is not
perfect determinism, however---and, on
the quantum scale, it would seem that the world is not very
deterministic at all. In any event, it is by
Heisenberg's uncertainty
principle, and by other arguments, impossible to have a completely
predictive physics. Thus, regardless of the question of determinism,
it is not overtly
paradoxical to believe in
materialism and in
free
will at the same time. While there is currently no satisfactory
explanation of free
will, we do know that the concept is not inherently
anti-scientific,
as has been claimed in the
past. Especially with the
advent of
quantum mechanics, it would do us well to reëvaluate our positions on
physics and determinism. Finally,
philosophers too infrequently
consider the
compatibilist possibility---that, somehow,
determinism
and
free will can
coëxist. This, I believe, will eventually
prevail---as a
coöperative effort, rather than a
compromise.
Works Cited
Dennett, Daniel C. Elbow Room: the
Varieties of Free Will worth Wanting. Cambridge, MA: the MIT
Press, 1984.
Descartes, René. Meditations on First
Philosophy. In From Descartes to Kant: readings in the
Philosophy of the Renaissance and Enlightenment.
Eds. T.V. Smith and Marjorie Green. Chicago: the University of
Chicago Press, 1940.
Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future
Metaphysics. In Smith and Green, eds.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. ``Necessary
and Contingent Truths''. In Smith and Green, eds.
Omnes, Roland. The Interpretation of Quantum
Mechanics. Princeton, NJ: the Princeton University Press, 1994.
Penrose, Roger. The Emperor's New Mind:
Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1989.
Saint-André, Peter. The Ism Book.
6 Dec. 2000 http://www.openthought.org/ismbook.
Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics. In Smith and
Green, eds.
Wilson, Margaret Dauler. Ideas and
Mechanism: essays on early modern philosophy. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1999.